\section{Quorum Systems} These definitions are taken from \cite{naor1998load} and \cite{vukolic2013origin}. % Given a set $X = \set{x_1, \ldots, x_n}$, a \defword{quorum system} over $X$ is a set $Q = \set{q_1, \ldots, q_m}$ of subsets of $X$, called \defword{quorums}, such that every pair of quorums intersect. That is, for every $q_1, q_2 \in Q$, $q_1 \cap q_2 \neq \emptyset$. A quorum system $Q$ is a \defword{coterie} if there does not exist quorums $q_1, q_2 \in Q$ such that $q_1 \subset q_2$. In other words, a coterie is a quorum system that does not contain some quorum $q_1$ that is a strict subset of some other quorum $q_2$. Let $P, Q$ be two coteries over the same set $X$. $P$ \defword{dominates} $Q$, denoted $P > Q$, if $P \neq Q$ and for every $q \in Q$, there exists some $p \in P$ such that $p \subseteq q$. A coterie $Q$ is \defword{dominated} if there exists some coterie $P$ that dominates it. \begin{example} Let $P$ be the majority quorum system over the set $X = \set{a, b, c}$. That is, $P = \set{\set{a, b}, \set{a, c}, \set{b, c}}$. Let $Q = \set{\set{a, b, c}}$. Note that both quorum systems are coteries. $P$ dominates $Q$. To see this, we first confirm that $P \neq Q$. Next, we consider every $q \in Q$ and find a corresponding $p \in P$ where $p \subseteq q$. Here, we only have one choice for $q$ (i.e. $q = \set{a, b, c}$), and for every $p \in P$, $p \subseteq q$. \end{example} There is an intuitive way to think about non-dominated coteries. A coterie $Q$ is non-dominated if (1) removing any element from any quorum would make $Q$ no longer a coterie and (2) there are no other quorums that we can add to $Q$ while preserving the fact that $Q$ is a coterie. Here's why. (1) Assume for contradiction that we remove some element from some quorum in $Q$ to form a new coterie $P$. $P$ dominates $Q$ in the obvious way, but $Q$ is non-dominated. (2) Assume for contradiction that we add some quorum to $Q$ to form a new coterie $P$. Again, $P$ dominates $Q$ in the obvious way, but $Q$ is non-dominated. Intuitively, a non-dominated coterie is a maximal coterie (we cannot add any more quorums) with minimal quorums (we cannot remove any elements from any quorums). \NOTE[michael]{% I think domination will be an important property for recursive quorum systems. I think there are some quorum systems that we cannot form as a recursive quorum system, but we can form a recursive quorum system that dominates it. The definition of domination that I found is only defined on coteries. Can we define this without coteries? I think so, but we have to double check. } Let $\sigma: Q \to [0, 1]$ be a discrete probability distribution over the quorums of $Q$ (i.e., $\sum_{q \in Q} \sigma(q) = 1$). We call $\sigma$ a \defword{strategy}. Intuitively, $\sigma$ is a strategy to pick quorums at random. We have the following definitions. \begin{align*} l_\sigma(x) &\defeq \sum_{\setst{q \in Q}{x \in q}} \sigma(q) \\ L_\sigma(Q) &\defeq \max_{x \in X} l_\sigma(x) \\ L(Q) &\defeq \min_\sigma L_\sigma(Q) \end{align*} $l_\sigma(x)$ is the load on $x$ given some strategy $\sigma$. $L_\sigma(Q)$ is the load on most loaded element $x$. $L(Q)$ is the \defword{load} of the best possible strategy. Intuitively, the lower the load of a quorum system, the higher the throughput it can support. \begin{example} Consider the majority quorum system $Q = \set{\set{a, b}, \set{a, c}, \set{b, c}}$ on elements $X = \set{a, b, c}$. Let $\sigma(\set{a, b}) = \sigma(\set{a, c}) = 0.5$ and $\sigma(\set{b, c}) = 0$. \begin{align*} l_\sigma(a) &= \sigma(\set{a, b}) + \sigma(\set{a, c}) = 0.5 + 0.5 = 1 \\ l_\sigma(b) &= \sigma(\set{a, b}) + \sigma(\set{b, c}) = 0.5 + 0 = 0.5 \\ l_\sigma(c) &= \sigma(\set{a, c}) + \sigma(\set{b, c}) = 0.5 + 0 = 0.5 \\ L_\sigma(Q) &= \max(1, 0.5, 0.5) = 1 \end{align*} The load of $Q$ with respect to $\sigma$ is 1, but the load $L(Q)$ is not 1 because $\sigma$ is not an optimal strategy. If we instead choose $\sigma_{\text{opt}}(-) = \frac{1}{3}$, the load is reduced to $\frac{2}{3}$ which is optimal. \end{example} The \defword{resilience} or \defword{fault tolerance} of a quorum system $Q$ is the largest number $f$ such that for every subset $F \subseteq X$ with $|F| = f$, there still exists some quorum $q \in Q$ such that $q \cap F = \emptyset$. Intuitively, a quorum system has fault tolerance $f$ if we can fail an arbitrary set of $f$ elements and still have some quorum left.